Sse.tongji.edu.cn

Norman, Donald, Things that make us smart.
Chapter 3.
The Power of Representation
The power of the unaided mind is highly overrated. Without external aids, memory, thought, and reasoning are all constrained. But human intelligence is highly flexible and adaptive, superb at inventing pro-cedures and objects that overcome its own limits. The real powers come from devising external aids thatenhance cognitive abilities. How have we increased memory, thought, and reasoning? By the invention ofexternal aids: It is things that make us smart. Some assistance comes through cooperative social behavior; somearises through exploitation of the information present in the environ- ment; and some comes through thedevelopment of tools of thought – cognitive artifacts – that complement abilities and strengthen mental powers.
The limits of the average mind are most easily demonstrated by noting the attention paid to those who have managed to over- come them. We pay homage to those who can remember large quantities of infor-mation without any external aid. We pay them money to perform before us on the stage, and we clapdelightedly when they learn the names of everyone in the room or tell us the cube root of the serial number of adollar bill held up by someone in the audience or tell us on what day of the week some arbitrary event a hundredyears ago fell. We admire these abilities because they are so unusual and so difficult for the average person toperform. Actually, these skills are difficult even for the expert. They take years to perfect; they require thememorization of numerous tables and word lists, and the learning and continued practice of the computationaland mnemonic algorithms. More important, however, is that these are unessential skills. The rest of us live quiteproductive lives without ever acquiring them. We substitute paper and pencil for mnemonic skills, pocketcalculators for computational skills, and printed calendars and tables for extensive memorization and mentalcalculation.
Probably the most important of our external aids are paper, pencil, and the corresponding skills of reading and writing. But because we tend to notice the unique, not the commonplace, few recognize them forthe powerful tools that they are, nor does the average person realize what break- throughs in reasoning andtechnology were required to invent writing, numerical representations, portable and reliable pens and pencils,and inexpensive, functional writing paper.
Oral cultures, societies that do not yet have a written language and that also lack the mechanical tools of technological cultures, do not share the benefits. These cultures have not developed advanced mathematics orformal methods of decision making and problem solving. The society that does not yet have writing also hasless formal schooling. Instead, most education is conducted through apprenticeships, by watching, copying, andbeing guided by those who know how to do the task being learned. Their need for formal schooling is limited.
They haven’t developed math- ematics or science, formal history, or extensive commercial records because theycan’t without the aid of artificially constructed artifacts. It is things that make us smart.
Two thousand years ago, Plato wrote the collected dialogues in which he presented the views of Socrates on the important issues of those times. Socrates, Plato tells us, argued that books would destroythought. How could this be? After all, books, reading, and writing are considered to be the very essence of theeducated, intellectual citizen. How could one of the foremost thinkers of civilization deny their importance? Socrates is famous for his dialogues between teacher and student in which each questions and examines the thoughts of the other. Questioning and examination are the tools of reflection: Hear an idea, ponder it, question it, modify it, explore its limit- ations. When the idea is presented by a person, the audience caninterrupt, ask questions, probe to get at the underlying assumptions. But the author doesn’t come along with abook, so how could the book be questioned if it couldn’t answer back? This is what bothered Socrates.
Socrates was concerned with reflective thought: the ability to think deeply about things, to question and examine every statement. He thought that reading was experiential, that it would not lead to reflection.
SOCRATES: Then anyone who leaves behind him a written manual, and likewise anyone who takes it over from him, on the supposition that such writing will provide something reliable and permanent, must be exceedingly simple-minded; he must really be ignorant of Ammon’s utterance, if he imagines that written words can do anythingmore than remind one who knows that which the writing is concerned with.
PHAEDRUS: Very true.
SOCRATES: You know, Phaedrus, that’s the strange thing about writing, which makes it truly analogous to painting. The painter’s products stand before us as if they were alive, but if you question them, they maintain a mostmajestic silence. It is the same with written words; they seem to talk to you as if they were intelligent, but ifyou ask them anything about what they say, from a desire to be instructed, they go on telling you just thesame thing forever. And once a thing is put in writing, the composition, whatever it might be, drifts all overthe place, getting into the hands not only of those who understand it, but equally of those who have nobusiness with it; it doesn’t know how to address the right people, and not to address the wrong. And when itis ill-treated and unfairly abused it always needs its parent to come to its help, being unable to defend or helpitself.
PHAEDRUS: Once again you are perfectly right.
Socrates was an intellectual, and to him thinking was reflection or nothing. He didn’t go for this experiential stuff. The worst kind of writing for people like Socrates would be novels, storytelling. A storyengages the mind in an experiential mode, capturing the reader in the flow of events. All such experientialmodes – music, drama, and novels – were considered to be the entertainment of the masses, not worthy ofserious respect. Socrates worried that reading would be too passive, an ac- ceptance of the thoughts of the writerwithout the chance to question them seriously.
In the Middle Ages, just the opposite was true. Reading was generally done aloud, often to an audience.
It was an active process, so active that Susan Noakes, in her analysis of medieval reading, points out “that it hadbeen recommended by physicians, since classical times, as a mild form of exercise, like walking.” Moreover, Noakes observes that the characteristics of a good novel today were unheard of in earlier times: “Today, many readers take as the hallmark of the good novel the way it propels them to read itcontinuously, without putting it down, from beginning to end. Readers of many late medieval books would havebeen forced, on the other hand, to read dis- continuously, stopping to puzzle over the relationship betweencomplement and text.” (The term complement refers to the dialogue provided through the illustrations andmarginal comments – illuminations and glosses – sometimes put in by the author, sometimes by the copyist,sometimes by other readers.) During the Middle Ages, readers were taught the rules of rhetoric and were implored to employ them with each sentence: mnemonics, to memorize and learn the material; allegory, to find the multiple levels ofmeaning hidden beneath the literal text; typology, to think in historical parallels. No text was thought to becomplete without mental elaboration in the mind of the individual reader or debates within the social groupthat might be listening to the read-aloud text.
Readers in the latter part of the Middle Ages did with books exactly what Socrates had claimed was impossible: They ques- tioned and debated each idea. True, the author wasn’t around, but in many ways thatmade the job more challenging, more interesting. Read a sentence, question it. Read a page, criticize it. No authors to object. No authors to refute your arguments with the force of their rhetoric. Readers were free todevelop their own objections and opinions without interference from meddling authors. Today we may haveregressed to match the fears of Socrates: We read too quickly, without questioning or debating the thoughts ofthe author. But the fault does not lie with the book, the fault lies with the reader.
Cognitive artifacts are tools, cognitive tools. But how they interact with the mind and what results they deliver depend upon how they are used. A book is a cognitive tool only for those who know how to read, buteven then, what kind of tool it is depends upon how the reader employs it. A book cannot serve reflectivethought unless the reader knows how to reason, to reflect upon the material.
The cognitive age of humans started when we used sounds, gestures, and symbols to refer to objects, things, and concepts. The sound, gesture, or symbol is not the thing itself; rather, it stands for or refers to thething: It represents it.
The powers of cognition come from abstraction and representation: the ability to represent perceptions, experiences, and thoughts in some medium other than that in which they have occurred, abstracted away fromirrelevant details. This is the essence of intelligence, for if the represen- tation and the processes are just right,then new experiences, insights, and creations can emerge.
The important point is that we can make marks or symbols that represent something else and then do our reasoning by using those marks. People usually do this naturally: This is not some abstract, academicexercise. Suppose Henri had an auto accident and is describing it to his friends. The description might gosomething like this: “Here,” Henri might say, putting a pencil on the tabletop, “this is my car coming up to a traffic light.
The light is green, so I go through the intersection. Suddenly, out of nowhere, this dog comes running across thestreet.” With this statement, Henri places a paper clip on the table in front of the car to represent the dog. “I jamon my brakes, which makes me skid into this other car coming from the other direction. We don’t hit hard, butwe both sit there stunned.” Henri takes another pencil and lets it represent the second car. He manipulates the pencil representing his car to show it skidding, then turning and hitting the other pencil. Now the tabletop has two pencils touchingeach other and a paper clip.
“The dog disappears,” Henri says, moving the paper clip off the table. “Then the light turns red, but I can’t move. Suddenly, this car comes rushing down the side street. It has a green light, but here we are, stuckright in the middle of the intersection. Boom, it hits us, like this” – and Henri uses his finger to show the thirdcar coming from the side and hitting the two pencils, scattering them.
In this scenario, the tabletop, pencils, paper clip, and finger are all used symbol- ically. They stand for the real objects – the street, the three cars, and the dog. In the listener’s head are other symbols to represent thestreets and the traffic light. Notice how difficult it would have been to tell this story without the artifacts,without the tabletop, pencils, and paper clip. In fact, you, the reader, may have had some problems following itin this text unless you tried to visualize the scene in your head: What was the path of the dog? Exactly wherewere the two cars stopped in the inter- section? How did the third car travel? The story on the tabletop helps show some of the simpler properties of artifacts. You can see how they help the mind keep track of complex events. The same represen- tational structure is also a tool for socialcommunication: Several different people can share the tabletop and the story at the same time, perhapssuggesting alternative courses of action. “Look,” Marie might say, picking up one of the pencils, “when yousaw the dog, you should have gone like this.” “Ah, but I couldn’t,” Henri might respond, “because there wasanother car there,” and he puts yet another pencil on the tabletop. The tabletop becomes a shared workspacewith shared represen- tations of the event.
Note what is now happening: People are using the artifacts themselves to reason about alternative courses of action. The representation substitutes for the real event. A problem, of course, is that therepresentations are abstractions. The pencil may represent the car, but it doesn’t have the correct size or mass. Itisn’t possible to show how fast the real car was going or how much it would skid if the brakes were applied. Allthis would require more powerful representations. Nonetheless, the representation adds dramatically to theperson’s power to describe the event. It enables other people to understand better. It makes it easier to analyzealternative actions. It adds power and precision to the memory of the unaided mind.
A good representation captures the essential elements of the event, deliberately leaving out the rest.
Pencils don’t look anything at all like cars, yet for the purposes of understanding the incident, that differ- encedoesn’t matter. A representation is never the same as the thing being repre- sented, else there would be noadvantage to using one. The critical trick is to get the abstractions right, to represent the important aspects andnot the unimportant. This allows everyone to concentrate upon the essentials without distraction fromirrelevancies. Herein lie both the power and the weakness of representations: Get the relevant aspects right, andthe representation provides sub- stantive power to enhance people’s ability to reason and think; get them wrong,and the representation is misleading, causing people to ignore critical aspects of the event or perhapsform misguided conclusions.
To understand cognitive artifacts, we must begin with an understanding of representation. A representational system has two essential ingredients, shown in figure 3.1: 1. The represented world: that which is to be represented; 2. The representing world: a set of symbols, each standing for something representing something in therepresented world.
Representations are important because they allow us to work with events and things absent in space and time, or for that matter, events and things that never existed – imaginary objects and concepts. Externalrepresentations, especially ones that can be part of a workspace shared with others, require some sort of constructed device to support them: an artifact. Even if the representation is as simple as stones placed in a special arrangement on the groundor a diagram drawn in the sand, its use as a representation is artificial, with a designated space and often with averbal explanation to interpret for each object in the representing world just what aspect of the representedworld it stands for. We have invented more powerful artifacts than sticks, stones, and sand, of course – artifactsthat support a variety of represen- tations, that are long-lasting, portable, easily reproduced and communicableover distances, and capable of powerful computational abilities in their own right.
The critical property of the represen- tations supported by cognitive artifacts is that they are themselves artificial objects that can be perceived and studied. Because they are artificial, created by people, they can takeon whatever form and structure best serves the task of the moment. Instead of working with the original idea,concept, or event, we perceive and think about representations that are better suited to match our thoughtprocesses. Figure 3.1 serves as an example of this ability to represent knowledge. The figure is itselfa representation, one that represents the concept of representation. It contains a representation of yet anotherartifact (labeled “The Representing World”) and the symbols on it, as well as the relationship between thatartifact and the world that it represents. Hence, the figure is a meta- representation: a representation of arepresentation.
This ability to represent the represen- tations of thoughts and concepts is the essence of reflection and of higher-order thought. It is through metarepresentations that we generate new knowledge, finding consistenciesand patterns in the represen- tations that could not readily be noticed in the world. These higher-order represen-tations are very difficult for the unaided mind to discover. In principle, it can be done without artifacts, with justthe unaided mind, but in practice, the limited ability to keep track of things in active consciousness severelyreduces that possibility.
Once we have ideas represented by representations, the physical world is no longer relevant. Instead, we do our thinking on the representations, sometimes on representations of representations. This is how wediscover higher-order relationships, structures, and consistencies in the world or, if you will, in representationsof the world. The ability to find these structures is at the heart of reasoning, and critical to serious literature, art,mathematics, and science. The ideal, of course, is to develop representations that • Capture the important, critical features of the represented world while ignoring the irrelevant• Are appropriate for the person, enhancing the process of interpretation• Are appropriate for the task, enhancing the ability to make judgments, to discover relevant regularities There are many kinds of artifacts. Expe- riential artifacts have different functions from reflective ones.
Experiential artifacts provide ways to experience and act upon the world, whereas reflective artifacts pro- videways to modify and act upon represen- tations. Experiential artifacts allow us to experience events as if we werethere, even when we are not, and to get information about things that would be inaccessible, even if we werepresent. A telescope gives us information about something distant in space. A movie or recording lets usexperience events distant in time and space. Instruments, such as the gas gauge of an automobile, give us information about states of equipment that would otherwise be inaccessible. Experiential artifacts thus mediatebetween the mind and the world.
Reflective artifacts allow us to ignore the real world and concentrate only upon artificial, representing worlds. In reflection, one wants to contemplate the experience and go beyond, finding new interpretations ortesting alternative courses of action. The process can be both powerful and dangerous. The power comes fromthe ability to make new discoveries. The danger occurs when- ever we fool ourselves into believing that therepresentation is the reality.
When we concentrate only upon the information represented within our artifacts, anything not present in the representation can conveniently be ignored. In actuality, things left out are mostly things we do not knowhow to represent, which is not the same as things of little importance. Nonetheless, things not represented fall inimportance: They tend to be forgotten or, even if remem- bered, given little weight. This is the lesson ofChapter 1: We value what we can measure (or represent).
Solving a problem simply means representing it so as to make the solution transparent. (Simon, 1981) Let’s play a game: the game of “15.” The “pieces” for the game are the nine digits – 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9. Each player takes a digit in turn. Once a digit is taken, it cannot be used by the other player. The first playerto get three digits that sum to 15 wins.
Here is a sample game: Player A takes 8. Player B takes 2. Then A takes 4, and B takes 3. A takes 5.
Question 1: Suppose you are now to step in and play for B. What move would you make? This is a difficult problem for several reasons, all traceable to the way I described the problem – to the representation. The task is described as a problem in arithmetic. To figure out what move to make, you have toconsider what possibilities both you and A have for winning. This requires a lot of calculation to determinewhich triples of digits sum to 15. There are few aids to memory, so it is difficult to keep track of which playerhas chosen which digits, which ones remain. I have deliber- ately presented the game information to you in arepresentational form that is awkward to use: The moves are listed sequentially, making it difficult to see justwhich digits A and B each have. Although the arithmetic is simple, keeping track of all the possibilities whiledoing the arithmetic makes the game difficult.
Now let’s play a different game, this one the children’s game of tic-tac-toe (also called “naughts and crosses” and “three in a row”). Players alternately place a naught (the symbol O) or a cross (the symbol X) inone of nine spaces arranged in a rectangular array (as shown in the following illus- tration). Once a space hasbeen taken, it cannot be changed by either player. The first player to get three symbols in a straight line wins.
Suppose player A is X and B is O, and the game has reached the following state: Question 2: Suppose you are now to step in and play an O for B. What move would you make? Unlike the game of 15, this time the task is easy. This is a spatial game, not one of arithmetic. To see what is happening, just look at the board: A quick glance shows that A is all poised to win (by completing adiagonal line of Xs) unless blocked by an O in the lower right-hand corner.
Question 1 was hard because the game of 15 requires reflection, with few external aids. Question 2 was easy because it could be answered experientially, perceptually: No computation required – just look at the boardand see the proper move.
But note, the two games are really the same. If you think of the nine digits of the game of 15 arranged in a rectangular pattern, you see that it is identical to the game of tic-tac-toe: Remember the moves in the game of 15? A had selected 8, 4, and 5; B had selected 2 and 3: Player B, you, had better select the digit 6, in the lower right corner. The two games are what we call “problem isomorphs” (from the Greek iso, for “the same,” and morph, for “form”). + Technically, questions 1and 2 are identical, but as the example shows, the choice of representation changes the task and the difficultydramatically.
Although the spatial representation of tic-tac-toe is much easier for people to play than the arithmetic one of 15, for computers the arithmetic representation is much easier. A computer program to solve tic-tac-toespatially would have to figure out whether the Xs and Os were on a straight line: It would have to solve thetrigonometric relationships among the points. How much easier for us, since we can simply look and see: Thehuman perceptual system is designed for this task. We find the method used by the computer difficult andcumbersome, although we are quite capable of programming the computer to follow the method. In return, it isvery difficult for the computer to do the perceptual processing.
This example illustrates two points. First, the form of representation makes a dramatic difference in the ease of the task, even though, technically, the choice does not change the problem. Second, the proper choice ofrepresentation depends upon the knowledge, system, and method being applied to the problem. In this case, themethod hardest for the human is easiest for the computer, and the method easiest for the human is hardest forthe computer. The example therefore also illustrates the differing yet complementary powers of human andcomputer information processing.
The power of a representation that fits the task shows up over and over again. Bad representations turn problems into reflective challenges. Good representations can often transform the same problems into easyexperiential tasks. The answer so difficult to find using one mode can jump right out in the other.
Consider the task of planning an airline trip between two cities. Suppose I want to travel from my hometown of San Diego (California, U.S.A.) to London (England, U.K.). The way in which airline informationis typically presented is shown in the accom- panying table: the format employed by the Official Airline Guide(the OAG), perhaps the most widely used source of airline infor- mation for professional travelers within theUnited States.
The OAG’s presentation is designed to pack as much information as possible into the smallest amount of space. The monthly worldwide edition is printed in tiny type on over fifteen hundred large pages. Although the publishers have done a creditable job of making the entries usable, the userstill has to do considerable mental processing and copying of information. The publishers have unwittinglytransformed the selection of a flight into a reflective task.
Suppose my desire is a flight that arrives in London late in the afternoon. At first glance, the OAG format would appear to be perfect because column four shows arrival time directly: I need only scan the arrivaltimes for the one most convenient. This would suggest the TWA flight that leaves San Diego at 9:00 in the evening and arrives in London at 8:30 in the evening the next day. Wonderful: I get on the plane, read a book,have a brief sleep, and when I get to London, clear customs, and get to my hotel, it is time for bed.
But is this true? Closer reading indicates that I had better not go to sleep right away: There is a plane change at Los Angeles. And there are two stops: Los Angeles and where? Is this flight longer than the others? While I want to arrive late in the afternoon, I do not want to spend several extra hours in traveling. So let me see which flight has the shortest duration. Now we see how the display affects the task: It was easy tosearch for a flight by arrival time, but it is not so easy to find a flight by duration. I have to do some arithmetic,subtracting departure times from arrival times, which is not easy given that they are on different days and thatthere is a seven-hour time difference between the two cities. + To do the arithmetic, I must invent an intermediate notation. Whenever an arrival occurs on the day following departure, add twenty-four hours to the arrival time: 1:00 AM the next day is 25:00; 8:30 PM the nextday is 44:30 (20:30 + 24:00). This puts arrival times in a format that makes it easy to find the differences intime between departure and arrival, and when I subtract the seven-hour time difference, I get the followingdurations: The TWA flight takes almost three hours longer than the others, so even though it arrives at a good time, the tradeoff of an extra three hours travel time is not accept- able. Note that this new arrival notation makes iteasier to do the arithmetic but harder to figure out what time the flights arrive. One table makes it easier tochoose the shortest flights; the other table makes it easier to check what time the flights arrive. Of course, Icould simply add an extra column to the first table giving duration, but in the crowded pages of the OAG, thereis simply no room for any information that can be derived.
All of this comparing and planning is reflective. I look at the information given in the OAG and ask questions of it, restruc- turing the information and performing new computations. This is an excellent exampleof the power of reflection, except it shouldn’t be needed. A different form for presenting this information wouldchange the task to an experiential one, where the answers would appear through inspection.
The OAG uses a table to present its information, and this made some of the comparisons difficult.
Stephen Casner has shown how the graphic presentation of scheduling information can simplify some of thedecision making in flight planning. + So, borrowing from his work, let us examine these three flights. (Seechart below.) This graphic display does appear to make some of the information about the flights much easier to comprehend. It shows all the information in the OAG display, plus more information about the stops. Durationsof the three flights are indicated by the lengths of the lines connecting departure and arrival times. The notationalso provides a simple way to represent plane changes (the “steps” in the lines) as well as the amount of timespent at stops (the gaps in the lines). The AA flight has a stop, plane change, and delay at Dallas/Fort Worth (DFW). The BA flight stops with a delay but no plane change at Los Angeles (LAX). The TWA flight has a plane change at Los Angeles and a stop with no plane change but a long layover in New York atKennedy airport (JFK).
Which is the shortest-duration flight? We have already discussed the difficulties of answering this question from the OAG table. In theory, the answer should be easy to discover in the graphic display because allthat needs to be done is to compare the lengths of the three lines. In practice, as you can readily see foryourself, the comparisons are not so easy to make. To compare flight durations, you must mentally line up thelines to determine which is the shortest. This example shows that perceptual processing alone does notguarantee success.
Whenever mental transformations are necessary in order to make comparisons of the configurations, graphic representation presents the viewer with a difficult task.
The comparison is finally transformed into an experiential task by lining up the starting points: Now you can just look and immediately see the answer.
The TWA flight is the longest, and the other two have approximately the same duration. Line up the starting points, remove some distracting clutter, and we have an easy task: The task that used to requirearithmetic in the table or mental superposition of lines in the other graphic display can now be done by simplyscanning the diagram to find the line that sticks out most (for the longest flight) or least (for the shortest flight).
This new representation also has another advantage. Because the flight times are given in local time, the flight duration is seven hours less than the lengths of the lines would suggest. To determine the actual amount oftime on the airplane, you have to subtract the seven-hour time difference. But with this new graph, even thesubtraction task is easy. We simply need to move the starting point for the comparison of the lines seven hoursto the right, as illustrated on the diagram.
What do we conclude about the appro- priate representation for a task? The answer depends upon the task. To know the class of service or the type of airplane, text is superior. To know the exact minute ofdeparture (11:31, say), the printed number is needed. To make a rapid comparison of flight duration, the graphicdisplay is best.
Now that we have seen how graphic displays can simplify the task, what should the OAG do? I recommend that it continue as it is. The publishers of the OAG have a different task from the users. They needto make available as much relevant infor- mation as possible. Space is clearly of great importance, and thetextual presentation the OAG provides is both efficient and relatively usable. The OAG has changed its formatover the years to improve the usability. The graphic display takes up much more space than the tabular one. Themost appropriate format depends upon the task, which means that no single format can ever be correct for allpurposes.
Someday, not too far in the future, all the information will be available on electronic devices whose displays will allow the same information to be presented in a variety of ways: different layouts for differentneeds. Wouldn’t it be nice to be able to see a listing of all flights organized by time of arrival or by duration offlight or by price of the ticket? Displays that let us switch instantly from numerical format to graphic, dependingupon the task? And that let us move among all the formats until all the information needed was available,neither too much nor too little? + HOW REPRESENTATIONS AID INFORMATION ACCESS AND COMPUTATION There are two major tasks for the user of an information display: 1. Finding the relevant information;2. Computing the desired conclusion; In our examination of information displays, we can note what kinds of assistance the displays provide for these two aspects: What aids are given to help the person’s access to the appropriate information? What aidsare given to help with the computations? Consider this example, taken from the draft of a Ph.D. dissertation: They found that while subjects would rate the analogies, from best to worst, as literally similar, true analogy, mereappearance, and false analogy, their recall for stories, from best to worst, was literally similar,mere appearance, true analogy, and false analogy.
Why is the sentence so unintelligible? Just consider what you have to do to figure out what it means: Best to worst, um, best for analogies is literally similar. And stories, best is literally similar. Gee, those are the same. Let’s see, next best for analogies is, um, true analogy. Next best for, um, stories, is, um, mereappearance. Hmm, that’s different.
The task of understanding the sentence is an example of reflective thought, unneces- sarily reflective, for the information in the sample sentence can also be displayed in a chart like this: The following diagrammatic format uses several techniques to aid the reader. The diagram contains exactly the same information as the original, written sentence, but in a form much easier to understand. Thetabular arrangement has made both the search and the computations – which, in this case, are comparisons –simpler. Is this a graphic, a chart, or a table? It doesn’t matter: It uses an appropriate display format for the task.
Medical prescriptions are growing ever more complex, with many people being required to take numerous medications daily. How well do people cope with following their prescriptions? Not very well.
Several surveys have shown that between 10 percent and 30 percent of the people studied were unable todetermine how much medication they should take at any time. In one study, arthritic patients were asked tobring their medication to the experimenters and then, with the bottles and containers in front of them, to writedown their daily medication. They were allowed as much time as needed. The results showed great difficulty indoing the task, with an average error rate of about 14 percent. It should hardly be a surprise that the moremedications prescribed, the greater the percentage of error. Those people who were prescribed the largestamounts (seven or more drug dosages a day) made both the highest absolute number of errors and the highestpercentage of errors: slightly over 30 percent.
The problems of keeping track of medication are well known. In my local drugstore, several different memory aids are available, all aimed at making it easier to keep track of pill taking. All of them are “pillorganizers,” boxes divided into com- partments labeled by time of day, day of week, or both day and time. Inprinciple, these should be beneficial to patients, once the pills are loaded into the proper com- partments. Alas,loading the boxes is not very easy. The boxes do not overcome the fundamental problems of interpreting theprescriptions.
The same study that revealed the 30 percent error rate in taking pills also examined how well patients could use these organizers. Again, the answer is not very well. One patient put twice the recommendedmedication into one of the boxes. Another box tended to be loaded properly, but the average loading time wasover nine minutes! These organizers do not appear to work, not when they still lead to errors or when theyrequire so much time to be loaded with pills.
This is an area crying out for help. Solutions, to be effective, must include and support the needs of all the people involved with the prescription: the patient, the physician and physician’s aides, and the pharmacist.
This issue can truly be a matter of life or death.
One of the problems is that the prescriptions themselves are not written from the patient’s point of view.
Consider the following medical prescription from the work ofpsychologist Ruth Day, a prescription that wasgiven to a patient following hospitalization for a mild stroke.
– 1 tablet every 12 hours (twice a day) This set of instructions is very difficult to follow. Speaking of the patient, Day reports: Over the next few days, he had difficulty remembering what pills to take, as well as what pills he had already taken. It would be easy to blame the patient: after all, he was 81 years old and had just had a stroke.
However, he was highly intelligent, was still working full time (and had even begun a new and demandingcareer a few years earlier), was not otherwise disoriented, and was highly motivated to return to work and anactive life style. (Day, 1988, p. 276) The physician’s list, as presented here, is neatly organized, precise, and easy to read. It is very similar to the format used for most prescriptions in the United States. The prob- lem is that it is set up for the wrong task.
The representation is appropriate from the point of view of the prescribing physician: Figure out what thepatient needs and write it down. But it simply does not lend itself to usage. The list is organized by medicine,which makes it easy for the physician and the pharmacist to look for any medication and see how it wasprescribed. But the patient needs it organized by time: Given the time of day, what actions should beperformed? Day tested the usability of the prescription by having people try to answer the following twoquestions: 1. It is lunchtime (noon). Which pills should you take? 2. If you leave home in the afternoon and will not be back until breakfast time the next day, how many pills of each type should you take along? As you can determine for yourself, it is not easy to answer these questions. The problem is that following this prescription is a reflective task, when it should be an experiential one. Reflection requires mentaleffort, something a sleepy, ill patient is apt to have trouble with. To fit the needs of the patient, the prescriptionshould be organized by time of day. Note this organization is still appropriate for the physician or pharmacist.
Here is Day’s suggested presentation of the information: Notice that with Day’s solution, the items can be organized by time of day (the columns) or by medication (the rows). The users simply scan the list by whichever starting point they prefer. A simple changein representation transforms the earlier, difficult reflective task into a much simpler experiential one. Day’sexperiments showed that the matrix form was not only easier but also conducive to more accurate inter-pretation than the original (and more common) format.
As Day points out, the matrix has major advantages over lists. Lists are organized by one factor (medication name, in this example). Matrices allow several different dimensions to serve as organizational keys:in this case, medication name or time of day. Whenever several different needs have to be met, a matrix is apt tobe superior.
The matrix organization aids both search and computation. In the original prescription, in order to answer the question “How many pills are taken at lunchtime?” the entire list had to be read and then interpreted.
The computations were reasonably extensive, even if simple in nature. With the matrix, the computa- tionmerely involves scanning down the “Lunch” column and counting. Once again, the proper choice of cognitiveartifact aids the task by transforming it from reflection to experiencing, simplifying the operations that must beperformed to reach the desired answer.
Imagine trying to multiply using Roman numerals – say, CCCVI times CCXXXVIII. It’s possible, but
very difficult. The same numbers written in modern notation – 306 times 238 – present an easier challenge. Themodern Arabic notation lends itself to efficient algorithms for arithmetic, although to multiply these three-digitnumbers will require writing something down. In Roman numerals, each symbol stands for a quantity, and intheir original form (where 4 was written as “IIII” and 9 as “VIIII”), it doesn’t even matter in what order youwrite the symbols: CCXXXVIII is the same quantity as ICVXIICXX. + With our modern Arabic numbers, wealso use the same symbols repeatedly, but the meaning of each symbol depends upon its location. That’s whywe need the 0 in 306: The 3 means “300” only in the third position from the right. Roman numerals had no needfor a zero.
The choice of representation for numbers makes a big difference in how easy or hard it is to do certain operations. Arabic numbers are not always the best choice for represen- tation.
One of the oldest forms of representing numerical quantities – tally marks – is still the best form when we need a way of counting something rapidly. To count an item, I make a short vertical line, |; adding a secondone, ||; a third, |||; and a fourth, ||||: one new mark for each new item.
Tally marks are easy to make and easy to compare, which is why they are still in use today. Roman or Arabic numerals are much more difficult. Why? Because tally marks are additive: With an additiverepresentation, if I wish to increase the value of a previous symbol, I simply add extra marks to the symbolalready there. Thus the symbol for 3 (|||) readily becomes the symbol for 4 (||||). Nothing already present has tobe changed.
Contrast this with Arabic numerals, which are substitutive: With a substitutive representation, if I wish to increase the value of a previous symbol, I must substitute a new symbol for the previous one. To increase thevalue by 1, I have to cross out the previous value and write the new one. The symbol 1 becomes ¡ 2, and then ¡ 2becomes ¡ ™ 3.
Of course, there are other differences between Arabic and tally representations besides the ease of making the marks. Arabic numbers are harder to make than tally marks, but easier to read and to use forcomputations. To make it easier to read tally marks, we usually modify them somewhat, so we group them intofives, generally like this: ||||. [in norman's book the cross-through is slanted] Additive notations have another important property: The size of the representation is proportional to the value of the number. So tally marks also serve as a graph. (See figure 3.2) These examples show that changes in representation often provide us with tradeoffs: One aspect of the task gets easier while another gets harder. Thus, while counting, tally marks are easier to make than Arabicnumbers and easier to compare, especially if the number of objects is relatively small. But for doingcalculations, tally marks are much harder to use than Arabic numbers.
Addition is easier with Roman than Arabic numerals. Strange as it may seem, it is easier to add
two numbers using Roman numerals than using our everyday Arabic numerals. Today students have to learn thearithmetic table: They start by learning the ten arbitrary symbols for the ten digits, then learn place notation toknow that 46 is the same as four 10s plus six 1s. Next, they must memorize the sums for the forty-five possiblepairs of numbers. (The ten digits, 0 through 9, have 100 possible combinations. But because of the propertycalled reflexivity – e.g., 4+5 = 5+4 – and the ease of adding zero, only forty-five combinations need to belearned.) Finally, students have to learn what to do if there is a carry from one column to the other. All thistakes a surprisingly long time to learn.
Roman students simply had to learn the Roman characters for digits – seven different characters go from 1 to 1,000 (I, V, X, L, C, D, M). After that, to add two numbers, they simply combined the symbolstogether and reordered them, all similar symbols together, the symbols with the greatest value on the left. Thenthey applied some simplification rules (one rule for each symbol) that tell how small symbols combine to makebigger ones (e.g., IIIII = V, VV = X). This is a lot less to learn than the ten symbols of Arabic numerals, theforty-five arithmetic combinations, and the rules for place notation and carry. It’s a lot easier too.
The problem: CCCVI + CCXXXVIII
CCCVICCXXXVIII
CCCCCXXXVVIIII
DXXXXIIII
No arithmetic sums have to be known, just how to combine, reorder, simplify, and read the symbols.
Roman children had it easier than today’s – at least, until they tried to multiply or divide.
ADDITIVE AND SUBSTITUTIVE REPRESENTATIONS The distinction between additive and substitutive dimensions is important, one that makes a big difference in the ease of understanding graphic representations. The distinction is not well respected by manygraphic designers.
Look at figure 3.3, my redrawing of a chart that was published in a newspaper. The chart uses different kinds of shading superimposed on a map of the United States to indicate what percentages of homesexceed the recommended level of radon, a radioactive gas that we all wish to avoid. Alas, the chart uses thewrong repre- sentation: A substitutive representation (different types of shading) is used to represent additiveinformation (percentage of homes that exceed the recommended level of radon). Look at that graph and try tofigure out where in the United States radon is most prevalent, least prevalent, and at an average value. The taskis hard because the shadings are arbitrary: You have to keep going back to the legend to remember whether aparticular shading represents a greater or lesser value than another. The choice of shading transforms this into areflective task when it should be experiential.
The proper way to draw the figure is to use an ordered sequence of density (an additive scale) to represent percentages (an additive dimension). Try the same task (to determine where radon is most prevelant,least prevalent, and at an average value) with the map shown in figure 3.4.
I have deliberately introduced a problem with the representation in figure 3.4 to emphasize the point about the importance of representational format. If you look at the map, it appears that the northwest part of theUnited States has a very low concentration of radon. That’s because that portion of the map is white, and on thescale of density, white falls to the left of (less than) the 0 – 10% density. In this case, however, white actuallyrepresents those states for which there are no data. A better way to make this graph would be to delete thenames of states for which there is no information. I left them in because the natural misinterpretation helpsmake the point about the impact of representational format.
Figure 3.3(left), with an inappropriate use of substitutive shading to represent additive percentages, makes the comparison task one of reflection. Figure 3.3(right), which uses an additive representation of shadingto represent the additive percentages, allows the task to be performed experientially.
Color (hue) is frequently used to represent density or quantity, especially in geographic maps, satellite photographs, and medical imagery. But hue is a substitutive repre- sentation, and the values of interest are usually additive scales. Hence hue is inappropriate for this purpose. The use of hue should lead to interpretivedifficulties. Many colorful scientific graphics, usually generated by a computer, use different hues to representnumerical value. These graphics force the viewer to keep referring to the legend that gives the mapping betweenthe additive scale of interest and the hues. Density, saturation, or brightness would provide a superiorrepresentation.
The several examples throughout this chapter illustrate an important design principle –naturalness: + Naturalness principle: Experiential cognition is aided when the properties of the representation match the properties of the thing being represented.
I return to these and other design principles in Chapter 4, but let us explore some of the implications of the principle. We humans are spatial animals, very dependent upon perceptual information. Representations thatmake use of spatial and perceptual relationships allow us to make efficient use of our perceptual systems, tothink experientially. Representations that use arbitrary symbols require mental transformations, mentalcomparisons, and other mental processes. These cause us to think reflectively, and although in many cases thisis appropriate and necessary, it is more difficult than experiential cognition. It is also subject to error, especiallywhen people are under high stress.
Mappings are the relationship between the format of the representation and the actual things being represented. They are easier, more reliable, and more natural with well-designed perceptual or spatialrepresentations than with abstract representations. This leads to the second principle: Perceptual principle: Perceptual and spatial representations are more natural and therefore to be preferred over nonperceptual, nonspatial representations, but only if the mapping between the representationand what it stands for is natural analogous to the real perceptual and spatial environment.
Graphs are often superior to tables of numbers because in a graph, the height of the line is proportional to the value, so you can compare the different values perceptually. If all you have to work with is numbers, thenyou have to do some mental arithmetic to see the relationships. Graphs are not always superior to tables, mindyou: only when the task is appropriate for perceptual judgments.
We have already seen that to decide whether one number is larger than another, tally marks are superior to Arabic notation because the length of the line of tally marks is directly proportional to the value represented.
You might very well wonder what the fuss is about here. The comparison of 23 and 12 seems natural andstraight- forward: 23 is larger than 12, what’s the big deal? The big deal is that numbers are really not natural.
They are reflective tools, not experiential ones. Powerful, essential tools for thought, but nonetheless, reflective.
When Arabic numerals were first invented, it was only the most highly educated people who could master them,and their use was debated and, in some cases, prohibited. Even today, it takes years of study in childhood tobecome proficient at arithmetic, years of practice that later on allow adults to regard the comparison as simpleand natural. Anything that requires that much study is not natural.
Much to many people’s surprise, experimental psychologists discovered that people can answer problem A faster than they can B. The time differences are small, small enough that you can’t notice it yourself, butlarge enough to be easily measured through the appropriate experiments. Even though we experience bothcomparisons as immediate and effortless, B takes more time and effort than A. Why is this? So far, the onlyanswer that accounts for all the findings is that the Arabic numbers are translated into a perceptual image – anadditive represen- tation – before the comparison is performed. The greater the perceptual difference, the easierthe task.
From a logical point of view, the two problems A and B seem equally easy. The point to learn from this is that real psychology is not the same as folk psychology or logic. People have their own commonsense viewsof how their minds work – a folk psychology. Alas, people are only aware of their conscious experiences, whichis a mere fraction of what really goes on. Commonsense views of psychological behavior are reasonable,sensible, and in agreement with everyday experience. Logical views are also reasonable and sensible. Bothcommon sense and logic are often wrong.
Here is the perceptual analog of the numerical comparison. In each problem, the lines are drawn to scale so that they match the earlier questions A and B. Try these two graphic comparisons: In A and B, which line islonger? The perceptual comparisons are simple and direct, but here, just as with the earlier questions A and B,comparison A can be done more rapidly than comparison B. But the graphic form of the comparison is easierand faster than the numerical one: The first is experiential, the other reflective. To compare the lengths of twolines, you don’t even have to know anything about numbers: The perceptual system handles the chore, simplyand efficiently.
Representations that match our perceptual capabilities are simpler and easier to use than those that requirereflection. Moreover, under a heavy work load (perhaps under severe stress, danger, and time pressure),representations that require reflection – such as the use of Arabic numbers – are not used as rapidly andefficiently as those that can be used experientially, through simple perceptual comparisons. Where simplecomparisons are required, graphic notation is superior. But where exact numerical values are required or wherenumerical operations must be performed, Arabic notation is clearly superior – that is why it is the standardnotation used today.
The power of cognitive artifacts derives from the power of representation. The form of representation mostappropriate for an artifact depends upon the task to be performed. The same information may need to berepresented differently for different tasks. With the appropriate choice of representation, hard tasks becomeeasy.

Source: http://sse.tongji.edu.cn/liangshuang/hci2013spring/readings/things-that-make-us-smart.pdf

Premedication for artificial joints

PREMEDICATION FOR ARTIFICIAL JOINTS The oral cavity is a portal of entry as well as the site of disease for microbial infections that affect general health. Streptococcus viridian is the main infective agent that can enter the bloodstream from areas with considerable bleeding such as the oral cavity, urinary tract and gastrointestinal tract. This bacteria may lodge on the heart valves, i

Microsoft word - gout remedy v 12.doc

Gout Remedy Note: For Those Who Are Suffering from the Painful of Gout: In this report, you’ll discover proven remedies to lessen the pain of your gout attacks and prevent gout from occurring. You’ll learn how to take control of your gout through proper medication, diet and preventive treatment. Beginning your treatment as quickly as possible can help you eliminate the severe pain as

Copyright © 2014 Articles Finder